Mathematical Induction



Contents...



Mathematical Induction | Proof


In this paper, we prove the basic notion of mathematical induction. This is a proof technique for proving various theorems. The basic rules for mathematical induction are base case, formalization, and induction. So, we start with a statement call it $S(1)$ that begins the induction. We always need to show that it is true and demonstrate what it is. Next, we start the formalization which is when we take the nth statement $S(n)$ and show how it can lead to $S(n+1)$. We show that if $S(n)$ is true, then $S(n+1)$ is true as well. From here, we have induction on $n$, which means that $S(n)$ is surely true for all $n \in \mathbb{N}$, so all natural values of $n$. To prove this theorem of mathematical induction, we will assume the base case and formalization are correct. So, we know the first statement is correct which means $S(1)$ is right. We also know that if $S(n)$ is true, then $S(n+1)$ is true as well, meaning $S(n) \to S(n+1)$. Now, suppose that for some number $\alpha \in \mathbb{N}$ that $S(\alpha) \to S(\alpha + 1)$ doesnʻt hold true. By observation, we know $S(1) \to S(2)$ and then $S(2) \to S(3)$, so in whole by observation, $S(1)$, $S(2)$, and $S(3)$ are all true. We can keep chaining like this up to $\alpha$ and find out from formalization that $S(\alpha) \to S(\alpha + 1)$ is true as well. But, we assumed previously that $S(\alpha) \to S(\alpha + 1)$ isnʻt true for some $\alpha$. This is a contradiction, so we know by contradiction that $S(n)$ is true for all $n \in \mathbb{N}$ under the conditions for mathematical induction, as desired. $\blacksquare$